Why Some Categories of Evidence are Fundamentally Weak: Anecdotal Evidence

 Very often we want to make claims about something. These claims might be explanations, interpretations, predictions, recommendations, strategies for action, propositions about states of affairs, judgements, assessments, and many more. Normally, we want to persuade or convince someone of the truth of our claims to invoke action. If your objective is to move someone to action, you might need to engage in means-end reasoning to get them to reconstruct their current goal structure. In other instances, we might want to convince someone of our position to gain alignment on a specific problem, without invoking action. Or we might investigate claims simply out of our intellectual curiosity to reduce uncertainty or gain understanding of a concept. All of this will eventually lead us to engage with someone else (written or verbal) in a discussion, dialogue, or argument. There are times during disagreement when the people you encounter might resort to coercion, manipulation, and deception in order to invoke action or confer notions of truth. Sometimes they might prove their position by assertion or resort to argumentation ad nauseam until their interlocutor concedes. The nature of assertion is interesting in that, it delivers no reason to accept the position on grounds of the statement alone; it's simply an expression of belief, preference, or desire. Assertions can range from simple atomic statements of fact such as "The table is brown" to more complex propositions containing entire paradigms "When price goes up, demand goes down". Assertions of the former kind are inevitable for establishing common ground, assertions of the latter are done as a short cut in reasoning. If you or someone are trying to establish a claim, the question becomes; what conditions enhance its acceptability? What are the necessary conditions that will drive someone to action? You could probably resort to persuasion techniques such as story telling, rhetorical techniques, and narrative techniques; these are the sorts of oratory that have moved people to action for millennia. They certainty can aid in enhancing the acceptability of your claim and have probably moved you to take action when hearing a claim leveraged by these techniques. Consider the genre of epideictic oratory; speech oriented towards praise or condemnation. There are in fact, no arguments present in speech like this. On the contrary, it's purpose is to speak to an audience already convinced of the underlying propositions. It enhances the degree of conviction towards the proposition; moving people to act a certain way. The audience’s goal structure is entirely aligned with the speaker; who amplifies the underlying value structure of the community by means of speech. Now the question becomes; when does "acceptability" overlap with "true propositional content"? You can use all the aforementioned techniques to convince someone of your position and yet never demonstrate the validity of your position. This is one of the key demarcations between something such as literature and political oratory versus genuine research methods. While the former is concerned with convincing others of the position by means of appealing to common virtues (as an example), the latter convinces us by implementing sets of procedures that are stance independent. But Claims demonstrated using research methods need not move anyone to action in the same way that persuasive speech moves us. What are some of the instantiations of this method of inquiry? I want to mention a fundamental form of persuasion that seems convincing at surface level and contrast it with research methods that at face value, seem to be similar.

Let’s think about the anecdote. You will constantly hear factual claims that are based on "evidence" that is anecdotal in nature. Someone eats 10 lemons and 5 avocados while bathing in essential oils; suddenly their cold disappears. This example is absurd (unfortunately not too unrealistic) but the logic is similar across an arbitrary set of similar cases; someone does something to alleviate a generic set of symptoms, eventually they feel better, and attribute it to their newly discovered method. Of course these sorts of things ignore regression to the mean and principles of randomized control trials. I don't really want to elaborate on why structured investigation of cause-and-effect will always outperform anecdotal reasoning. What I want to do is probe into the question; why do anecdotes convince people? If we think about the structure of the anecdote, its acceptability dramatically changes depending on the content within it. Reconstruct the anecdote I gave above saying; Someone takes a multi-vitamin, sits in a sauna, and eats a piece of red meat. This immediately becomes more plausible despite it having the exact structure and lack of scientific rigor. The degree to which the anecdote corresponds with whatever is deemed "common sense", the more acceptable it will become. You can imagine that my reconstructed anecdote will not be convincing to a group of vegans, considering they do not share the presupposition that red meat is a possible cure. Let’s now restate the anecdote as; Someone drinks 5 cups of orange juice, detoxes, and meditates. This immediately becomes more plausible to a certain subset of people more aligned to this "common sense". This is one of the incredible drawbacks of even the most convincing anecdote; plausibility does not matter when it comes to factuality. The randomized control trial supersedes all of this because it is a demonstrated method that repeatedly returns reliable results contrary to notions of plausibility. So here is the first thing with the anecdote; it is incredibly unreliable in this respect. But we are at an impasse, so to speak. All empirical research relies on sense experience (albeit in an incredibly more structured and robust way) but so does anecdote, which is why people can get away with saying "it worked for me". How can we get passed this, so someone unfamiliar with rigorous methodology and research methods can understand why "worked for me" misses the point and that anecdotes are fundamentally flawed?

I think part of the problem comes from the very subtle ambiguity with the concept "evidence". Many people learn about the concept outside of a scientific context and then extrapolate their misunderstandings into what they presume science to be. Many people think that "proof" is something you do as in "winning a debate" (in which personal experience through anecdote might convince an audience). This is what I mentioned before, convincing someone of your position using a whole host of rhetorical methods. Evidence Law obviously tries to alleviate this by setting out burden of proof, rules of admissibility, authentication, and procedure regarding what is considered "relevant" evidence within a court of law. You cannot extrapolate this to the scientific domain; the two are answering different questions and therefore the conditions of acceptability will be different. Suppose someone is tried for a murder; there will be many sources of evidence admitted into the court including physical and undoubtedly some sort of testimonial evidence. Someone will be brought in to testify whether an event or part of an event occurred; their testimony is then assessed relative to the entire "Story" (sequence of facts). Sometimes testimony can be pivotal in determining a case; sometimes it is highly suspect subject to hearsay, issues with eye witness memory, leading questions, and all of the biases we have discovered in the past century demonstrating the unreliability of testimony. Now contrast approach this with a scientific investigation; Does aromatherapy reduce chronic pain? The structure of the question is fundamentally different. In the legal case we are asking whether person X was the cause of person Y's death, while the scientific case is asking whether we can make a causal generalization that X causes Y. The question is not "did this event in the past happen" but "does this treatment bring about this hypothesized cause under such-and-such conditions" (factual claim vs empirical generalization). We are in an entirely different domain, and I don't think people really grasp that. So, the anecdotal evidence "it worked for me" is entirely irrelevant because this is not a court case; your testimony is fundamentally weak when we are unconcerned with generalization. A single story reflecting your perceived experience is incredibly weak when it comes to generalization. Research does not go about by arguing over whose anecdote is more persuasive; it appeals to objective methods that supersede narration and argumentation. It relies on data collection and measurement, inferring conclusions from accepted methods, and being cautious to assert generalizations in the absence of replication.

We should probably ask ourselves what even is an anecdote? An anecdote is "a story with a point", their purpose is to communicate an idea using narrative. The anecdote may contain factual features, but frequently are subject to embellishment, narratology, ambiguity, lack of precision etc., all the features antithetical to scientific evidence. Think of an anecdote simply as a vessel that supports the transference of information. The term "anecdotal evidence" is somewhat of a misnomer, because anecdotes are not evidence according to the scientific sense of the term (and to a large extent the legal sense of the term). If scientific investigation seeks to understand the typicality of a relationship to infer cause and effect, by the very nature of an anecdote, it cannot achieve this because these are stories, not repeated measurements. Anecdotes can sometimes be used in the form of testimonials to entice someone into action; and might help you determine a course of action in informal settings. Consider a potential employee applying for a position. The prospective employer calls the applicants references to determine whether he is a "good fit". The references tell a couple of stories to demonstrate his qualities. The prospective employer then must decide based on this and other information he has access to. Thinking about this from a scientific perspective, "good fit" is not well defined enough to construct a measure. Furthermore, acquiring the data that represents "good fit" might be difficult. The nature of scientific inquiry is to generate data in such a way that it works with a statistical hypothesis test, while assessing testimony is an assessment of stories; in this case to determine whether you want the candidate to fill the position. You are determining their "worth" and inferring character, not their "objective qualities". Notice how employers never seek to verify whether the candidate performed the work they listed on their resume; so, it's not investigative either. The applicant signaling, through a variety of means, to the employer that they should get the job. In other words, it is a sales pitch (you are selling your labor to a potential buyer). This is not in the realm of "proof". We often use that term very loosely to gain leverage in conversations with people we disagree with. Advertisements also have this persuasive form. Note that I am not saying anecdotes are useless; they are however extremely useless when demonstrating a proof or statistical generalization. They simply do not fit into the form of scientific procedure; in fact, scientific procedures are meant to correct for the sorts of obvious issues that anecdotes fall prey to. To begin, scientific procedures correct for the inherent ambiguity, imprecisions, and vagueness of anecdotes by constructing measures that can be accessible to a universal audience. Observations are systematically recorded, rather than selectively presented as in the case of anecdotes. Results and procedures are documented in a structured way free of rhetorical devices and free from the issues with oral transmission. Results go through a process of peer review and replication to show that the results under discussion are robust to alternative model specifications and free of obvious error. Scientific methods seek to eliminate the selection bias, availability heuristic, placebo effects, lack of control, misrepresentations, memory issues, and generally just all of the ways we can be fooled by sense impression or dogmatic argument. Think of scientific methods as a collection of structured methods of investigation that improve our chances of being correct. It does this by explicitly correcting for obvious ways we can be wrong, such as an anecdote. I am not trying to rip on anecdote as being functionally useless; it’s not like I don't rely on them to gain inspiration, improve my skills, nudge me in a direction, decide which food to get at a restaurant etc. I am just saying that stories are inconsistent with the structure of experimentation, the ultimate procedure that buttresses our best theoretical explanations of the world. I'll provide a quick summary below:

Statistical methodologyAnecdotal evidence
Samples are large and representative. Typically, they are generalizable outside the sample.Small, biased samples are not generalizable.
Scientists take precise measurements in controlled environments with calibrated equipment.Unplanned observations are described orally or in writing.
Other relevant factors are measured and controlled.Pertinent factors are ignored.
Strict requirements for identifying causal connectionsAnecdotes assume causal relationships as a matter of fact.

The notion of statistical validity preoccupies scientific dialogues. At first glance you will notice that anecdotes completely fail when it comes to the reliability category if considered a form of data or evidence. They immediately fail the specificity category as well because definitionally, anecdotes are unspecific. Accuracy is typically failed because anecdotes are riddled with systematic errors, because by their very nature they are unsystematic.

You will occasionally come across a person claiming that "The singular of data is anecdote" or "the plural of anecdote is data"; this couldn't be farther from the truth. In fact, the inverse is what is actually true. Remember what was stated in the beginning, suppose you wish to convince someone of the truth of your claim. You could resort to constructing a story indicating why you believe it to be true. This can be in the form of anecdote or testimony. Suppose you ate an avocado and subsequently "felt better". Three of your friends have also "felt better". This "corroboration" convinces you of your position, and you wish to induce your interlocutor to action by using your anecdote, along with the others, as favorable to your conclusion. This is no doubt, information. Any word uttered can be thought of as "information" in the broadest sense; some representation that contains content. Data is a more encompassing concept, it expresses information in such a way that makes it amenable to analysis. Consider the example above, the information yielded will simply be "I ate an avocado and felt better". Contrast that with the sort of information scientific inquiry requires to extrapolate out of sample. Also consider the fact that "feeling better" does not constitute an objective measure of whether the treatment induced a positive response; all you have done is show that a few people have subjectively felt better. In order to determine if "the thing works", you will have to appeal to a measure beyond that which is subjectively assessed by the individual and propose/test a causal mechanism in which it could occur. Think about someone who claims to have a headache, attributes the root cause to brain cancer, and then does something arbitrary to alleviate the symptoms, claiming it as causally effective. Anecdote explicitly suppresses the actual scientific inquiry needed to establish the generalization; appealing to "how one feels" will necessarily obfuscate the actual effect. In this case, anecdote does not yield any relevant information; all it does is potentially direct further inquiry in which actual investigation can occur (this is the stage we attempt to generate evidence). But this is pragmatic, not evidential. It can help us form initial hypotheses, like all experience; but it is not substitutable or synonymous with evidence. They can also provide a context to make sense of established evidence. This is important because evidential inquiry can sometimes be abstracted from ordinary experience; the anecdote draws the analysis back into the existential realm. But again, this is rhetorical.

I bring up the latter in response to the article I've listed below "Sorry folks, The Plural of Anecdote is Data". If you google this quote you will find about half of the results claiming that "The plural of anecdote is NOT data" and the other half claiming that this was a misquote; the original source saying, "The plural of anecdote IS data". Regardless of whether it is a misquote, this does not admonish the fact that multiple anecdotes are undeniably NOT data. Besides, whether it is misquoted completely misses the point: the original proponent of the quote was wrong. Claiming it was a misquote masquerades the fact that the concept they are defending is fundamentally incorrect and does not stand as an argument in favor of its validity. I am not sure why intelligent people get this wrong. If your 3-year-old child gives you an anecdote about their invisible friend, does this constitute evidence in favor of the proposition that invisible beings permeate through the universe and have special connections with children? There is a huge conflation among "information yielded" and "evidence" or "data"; managing concept creep would probably help alleviate this problem. The assumption that "all information yielded" constitutes evidence completely misunderstands why the demarcation is necessary for valid inference. Now I think that this article provides a wonderful case for their position, until the point where the author conflates "data point" and anecdote. But the very next paragraph the author reinforces my point that anecdotes are simply heuristics that point our attention towards possible hypotheses; they are pragmatic assistants guiding the exploration phase but NOT the inference phase (that is where actual evidence comes). The author later refers to an example where anecdotes led to the falsification of a specific hypothesis; but he is mistaken. It was the anecdote that directed our attention to the possible flaws in current methodology which had the effect of convincing us to reassess our initial understanding of the ACTUAL evidence. A poorly conducted experiment or flawed analysis does not mean that the evidence was undermined by the anecdote; it simply directed our attention to our flawed analysis and prompted a revision. But again, this is not to say that anecdotes are in and of themselves evidence; they are still at their very core stories. A story is not a measurement, but it can prompt investigation and convince us we ought to perform a rigorous measure. This is the rhetorical effect of anecdote; it is behavior inducing. There comes a point where the author and I completely diverge from our understanding when they say "but numerous, similar anecdotes can inform the development of a hypothesis". It is true that "similar" anecdotes, however we define story similarity, can prompt us to investigate certain claims; but there are classes of claims that are inherently deemed implausible based on their epistemological status of the investigator regardless of the frequency. Consider the Miracle of the Sun, many people claimed, with very similar anecdotes, to see the literal emergence of the Virgin Mary in the sky; but many would nevertheless dismiss this on grounds of diverging philosophical and religious backgrounds. It would simply be impossible according to some belief systems and therefore not constitute a dataset despite the sheer number of similar anecdotes. Of course, this event yields some information about something; the mental states of the villagers, the status of Catholicism in Europe, or the degree of conviction in the prophecy. But the actual content of the anecdote does not yield any information amenable to analysis. Lets put it another way; if many people claim that they have had an encounter with a polar bear somewhere in Mexico, does this constitute a dataset in favor of that proposition and are you willing to pursue it as a hypothesis? No, because we know from evidence that polar bears cannot survive in such a climate. You will immediately disregard it on grounds of implausibility; evidence does not have this epistemological status. Sure if there is an anomalous record in the dataset you can question whether there was a measurement error, but this is not the same as dismissing or accepting a story as evidence on the basis of plausibility. It actually scares me that people cannot distinguish the two concepts; this is probably why there is social contagion of things we know with certainty are incorrect. Now there are instances in which many people claim something, which turns out to be the case. No one is denying that. There are, however, many instances in which anecdotes conflict, are ambiguous, unverifiable. There are instances where many people concede, through anecdote, to the truth of something which turns out to be demonstrably false. A quick look at the issues with eyewitness testimony explicitly show the utter unreliability of considering this as evidence (See the innocence project which shows that the majority of DNA exonerated cases were due to faulty eye witness memory). You should look at the research of Elizabeth Loftus, its quite extraordinary. This is why witnesses are deemed lower on the hierarchy of evidence unless we have specific evidence to demonstrate the reliability of their testimony showing that they were in a position to know what it is they have claimed; that it is not hearsay. This is one of the problems with anecdote is that its very difficult to discern from cultural knowledge simply being restated versus an actual experience. But this is my whole point; data is more than "information yielded" and anecdotes are incredibly unreliable especially for establishing a causal generalization.

To quote the authors incompetence: "But take a lot of observations that are similar in nature (or mutually-supporting) and suddenly you have the baseline data necessary to start developing a hypothesis. Anecdotes can, and do, provide a valuable information source at the initiation of a scientific investigation of a phenomena, or put another way: the plural of anecdote is indeed data". But this is fundamentally correct; anecdotes are not data. As the author explicitly states, anecdotes are just information that might inform a hypothesis. I am not just stating the obvious; that we are biased, poor at processing information, and poor reasoners. These are no doubt even more of a reason to be highly suspicious of anecdotes. I am going even further; the very nature of anecdote is antithetical to evidence. Honestly, even calling it information is a stretch; because information implies a sort of structure and context associated with data. Anecdotes are not even that. When I say "information yielded" I literally mean just that; something projected into the universe. I am not even willing to grant that anecdotes are a sort of qualitative data because anecdotes lack the rigor which qualitative data collection requires. I will talk a bit more about this later in the context of case studies and qualitative research.

But what kind of anecdotes are candidates for hypothesis formation? It seems conditional on the nature of the anecdote, the degree to which you find it "plausible". As I mentioned before, anecdotes are not useless. Anecdotes are one of the key mechanisms by which we communicate and interact with one another. If you are a parent, when your child comes home from school and shares their experience, it will be in the form of an anecdote. Do I simply tell him to prove what he is saying? That is silly. However, if my son tells me his teacher reprimanded him and that "she always has it out for him", are his isolated instances evidence of the teacher’s misbehavior? If he comes home and tells me his teacher was making a deal with the Mexican cartel at lunch on the basis that a Mexican person left her office, and that his friends corroborated this, am I seriously supposed to call this "evidence"? Proponents of "anecdote is evidence" will cite the fact that researchers engage in case studies prior to systematic investigation, "proving" that anecdotes are useful. Again, this is a serious point of confusion; case studies are systematic investigations with rules and structure, not ad hoc story telling. I will dive into this deeper later. For now you can take a look at "11 reasons to be skeptical of Uncontrolled Testimonials about health benefits of any product or service".

A lot of these arguments revolve around whether N=1 is sufficient for inference, but this still misses the point that anecdotes are not systematic measurements. While it is true that single observations cannot support generalizations, this critique ignores the fact that sample size is irrelevant when the "data" is not generated by a process, when the thing under discussion is a story. For example, if I watch an advertisement that provides an anecdote from one person claiming the product was amazing, and then watch a competing advertisement with ten anecdotes claiming the product is amazing; I will not weigh the alternative favorably simply because there are more anecdotes. The reason being is that its fundamentally an appeal to popularity, an appeal to the masses, or an appeal to authority; a persuasive marketing tactic specifically designed to entice us to purchase the product. The anecdotes are not evidence; the structure of the information is fundamentally unreliable. Furthermore, anecdotes of this nature do not come from identical conditions that "generated the story". In statistics the observations need to come from identical distributions; this is important because you need to be modeling the same process across all observations. There is no guarantee of this with anecdotes. Another problem with anecdotes is the lack of uniformity in their strength of conviction. What I mean by this is that say you have 10 anecdotes, 5 of them "are negative" and 5 of them "are positive". The way the anecdotes are worded or delivered impacts their believability. At face value, we would be indeterminant in what to believe based on the numbers. If we dive in and listen to the specific wordings and find that the 5 negative examples are "more compelling" in the language they choose to describe their experiences, we might weigh this more heavily in the negative cases favor. In fact, even if the numbers were skewed positively, due to loss aversion, negative examples will still outweigh the positive instances. Our minds are psychologically predisposed to be averse to negative outcomes; negative examples impact our behavior more radically than positive ones. So you can see, when we have multiple conflicting anecdotes, comparability becomes almost impossible. Furthermore, the way anecdotes are expressed (how the stories are told) and who tells the story, impacts their believability and plausibility. Actual evidence and data do not suffer from limitations like these. This is because anecdote is tied up with nebulous notions such as trustworthiness of the speaker, internal consistency of the story, degree of conviction (impacted by colorful language), supposed credibility/reliability of the speaker, and many other factors that vary the strength of believability. This is exactly why advertisements use anecdotes; they don't prove anything they just get people to consider buying the product. Anecdotes may also have a sort of argumentative structure underlying the story, which if unnoticed, can mistake someone into confusing anecdote with evidence. Consider someone gives an anecdote claiming that some "holistic" medical treatment "works for them". You search the medical literature and find scant evidence showing whether there is an effect; there just simply has not been any research done on the topic. The person giving the anecdote states that because it has not yet been proven false, it must be true; a classic argument from ignorance. Does this "testimony" count for anything, given that it’s an argument and a fallacious one? There should be some way to discern which anecdotes are reports of experience versus which anecdotes are arguments from experience. A corollary, there should be some way to differentiate valid from invalid experience. As a corollary, there should be a way to clarify and disambiguate the description of the experience. Another corollary, we should be conscientious of the fact that a statement of an experience is not equivalent to the truth of the content of the experience.

Referring back to the definition of anecdote, that which is a simple story, lets contrast it with a data generating process. Let’s first consider it in the context of a social science survey; I wish to understand sentiment among some population related to some topic. How can I do this? I've listed below survey methodology. One prompts a subject, randomly (ideally) selected from a target population, a series of questions intended to illicit responses that measure some sort of internal state unavailable to the interviewer. The idea is we are attempting to measure a construct in which one can infer something about the subject. In the case of close ended survey questions, the values can be converted into numerical categories than are amenable to statistical analysis. In the case of acquiring verbal feedback through open ended questionnaires, you need to avoid doing things like asking leading questions. There are guidelines for the wording/ordering of the questions. Attrition and non-response are issues that are taken into consideration, as well as validation of the self-report. Constructing a Questionnaire for open ended questions are notoriously difficult because you are, very often, not measuring the construct you intend on measuring. Contrast this with data collection for a physical experiment. If I want to infer something about the properties of a lake (or something else random), perhaps I will need to take a few measurements of key features to construct an index that aggregates the information together. I dip my little thermometer into the lake to measure the temperature. My apparatus measures the kinetic energy and gives me a reading. Boom. Now think about the open-ended questionnaire; you ask 100 different people what happened, and you will get 100 different variations of a response. There is no consistency; the language in one response will conflict with another. In other words, the data you are generating are extremely noisy and you are specifically probing in order to acquire information; in other words there is an interpretive process on the receiving end that can impact the response. There is a decoding process that has to be done in order to comprehend or interpret whatever is being said on both ends; receiver and sender. This is incredibly different from a measurement done within the realm of natural sciences. In the case of measuring heat, there is an explicit data generating process that creates the measurement "heat", the movement of molecules. The questionnaire however, probes for an answer; the response is a function of the quality of the question and many other factors such as context, location, background presuppositions etc. This is also the best-case scenario for measuring something that is "communicative" in nature. Now contrast this with ad-hoc storytelling in the form of anecdote. You and your friend are deep in conversation; their position on a topic is very passionate. You can begin to see hints of persuasive tactics, such as appealing to shared experience and authority. They eventually convince you of their position; the story convinced you. But is this the same as acquiring data from a questionnaire or something else systematic? No, this is poetic oratory.

Now this is not to say that textual information is void of usefulness. In my field of data analytics, we occasionally use information gathered from free-text fields that are typically reviews of a product or something about consumer engagement. You can do these sorts of analyses on tweets; pool together a collection of text and conduct a sentiment analysis (classic text mining analysis). This can give you a sort of indication as to the motivations and intent of people tweeting. When I worked in finance this was a frequently used analysis. Some hedge funds have data feeds that connect directly to opinion articles delivered by Bloomberg and Reuters; they run automatic sentiment analysis to get a sense of what people are perceiving about the market. Another big one was the speeches given by the chairmen of the Fed; we would frequently want to know if their words were "hawkish" or "dovish". These analyses are useful in that it can give you a general feel for the sentiment on a topic without having to directly sample a target population and do a proper statistical study. Another application of NLP techniques is that of topic modeling using Latent Dirichlet allocation. Using this technique, you can acquire multiple documents (possibly containing anecdotes), form a corpus, calculate statistics such as term-frequency inverse document frequency, and determine which topics regularly occur in a in the collection of text. You can do all sorts of tasks; named entity disambiguation, clustering, coreference, etc. Despite all of the interesting analytical techniques you can do with various collections of text, none of these techniques can demonstrate the truth of the propositional content within the corpus. What I mean by this, is that suppose you have a collection of anecdotes claiming that taking some medicine cures cancer; no NLP technique can demonstrate the internal validity of the anecdotes. Furthermore, having many of these anecdotes does not provide evidence in favor of the truth of the propositional content. Multiple anecdotes are just that; anecdotes. None of these analyses actually give any insight into the validity of the claims. You actually have to probe into the content of the claim, collect evidence and data, then discern its validity by measurement and experimentation. What these techniques do however, is tell us something about the people making the claims, or the collection as a whole. Take the example of sentiment analysis on the market opinion articles. Suppose the opinion pieces consist of anecdotes claiming that some policy had some causal effect on the markets. This would not constitute evidence that the causal effect had occurred, but it does indicate how actors in the market might respond to the general opinion. In other words, it will affect your investing strategy, but cannot prove the causal effect. It can only tell you that people believe the causal effect occurred. It goes without saying, the belief that something occurred is not a demonstration that something occurred. What if half of the opinion articles are simply restating what the other half had originally published, and the other half was the original source of their opinions? Not only does it not demonstrate anything, it provides little information gain. A collection of anecdotes does not give you insight into whether the thing stated is true or false, it gives you insight into a specific type of herd behavior. So, this is not to say that anecdotes and textual data is useless, it is just useless as a source of evidence when attempting to demonstrate the internal validity of its own content.

So, as we have seen, anecdotes cannot be used in scientific contexts. Are anecdotes synonymous with testimony? Not quite. Testimony is the “attestation of the truth of a matter”, but this is quite vague and general. In a legal setting, testimonials are declarations of fact. Note that these are simple facts, they cannot be causal generalizations. It is important to distinguish between various types, such as expert testimony. In virtue of their education, certifications, skills, or experience, a person is deemed an expert on a topic and is granted permission to give an assessment of the evidence under discussion. This is an important distinction; they are assessing and interpreting ambiguous evidence that could point in multiple directions and providing a likely explanation. Consider someone who is a ballistics expert; they can make crucial discernments that could lead a jury to reconsider their judgments. You would assess their judgments with a set of criteria that is different than the assessment of data. This falls under the argument from expert opinion, a form of argument from authority.

  • Major Premise: Source E is an expert in subject domain S containing proposition A.
  • Minor Premise: E asserts that proposition A (in domain S) is true (false).
  • Conclusion: A may plausibly be taken to be true (false)

Arguments from authority are obviously not “proof” of the content in the proposition. These arguments obviously beg the question, why and how did the authority determine this conclusion? These arguments can become fallacious very quickly if we merely assert “it is true because authority X says so”. No authority can confer the “truth” of a proposition; they must resort to methodology which justifies the inference. In other words, asserting X does not make X true just because it comes from someone we think is reliable. Nevertheless, arguments from authority are incredibly useful heuristics we can use in a knowledge economy where it is impossible to have expertise on everything that might be relevant in a situation. These arguments are not anecdotes but suffer the same issue; asserting something is true is not a demonstration of its truth. They are far more reliable than anecdotes however since there are exclusion criteria that reduce the odds of someone giving testimony who doesn’t have the relevant background knowledge. There are some basic questions you can ask before accepting expert opinions.

  • 1. Expertise Question: How credible is E as an expert source?
  • 2. Field Question: Is E an expert in the field that A is in?
  • 3. Opinion Question: What did E assert that implies A?
  • 4· Trustworthy Question: Is E personally reliable as a source?
  • 5· Consistency Question: Is A consistent with what other experts assert?
  • 6. Backup Evidence Question: Is E's assertion based on evidence?

Expert testimony is used for specific reasons, to achieve specific goals in a line of inquiry. Likewise, basic testimony also is used to achieve specific goals in a line of inquiry, establishing basic facts. Note that this is not the same as an anecdote because there are strict rules (in a court of law) restricting testimony from becoming speculative or emotive. Anecdotes necessarily have these sorts of elements as part of the entire story structure. Testimony is based on the argument from position to know (expert testimony is a subset of this sort of argument).

  • Major Premise: Source a is in a position to know about things in a certain subject domain S containing proposition A.
  • Minor Premise: a asserts that A (in domain S) is true (false).
  • Conclusion: A is true (false).
  • CQ1: Is a in position to know whether A is true (false)?
  • CQ2: Is a an honest (trustworthy, reliable) source?
  • CQ3: Did a assert that A is true (false)?

So you can see there are some basic questions we can ask to probe into the soundness of the argument structure. Accepting testimonial evidence in a court is based on the presumption that we can ascertain some information about states of affairs unavailable to investigators by asking people. Another related argument scheme that is a variation of the argument from position to know, is the argument from witness testimony.

  • Position to Know Premise: Witness W is in a position to know whether A is true or not.
  • Truth Telling Premise: Witness W is telling the truth (as W knows it).
  • Statement Premise: Witness W states that A is true (false).
  • Conclusion: A may be plausibly taken to be true (false).
Critical Questions:

  • CQ1: Is what the witness said internally consistent?
  • CQ2: Is what the witness said consistent with the known facts of the case (based on evidence apart from what the witness testified to)?
  • CQ3: Is what the witness said consistent with what other witnesses have (independently) testified to?
  • CQ4: Is there some kind of bias that can be attributed to the account given by the witness?
  • CQ5: How plausible is the statement A asserted by the witness?

These are just some of the basic questions you should ask before considering whether to accept a testimonial about an alleged fact. I mentioned above that witness testimonials are notoriously unreliable. This is based on the enormous amount of research pointing to the conclusion (think of the innocence project). However, This sort of testimony could be reliable under very specific conditions, like all forms of evidence. Personal factors such as confidence of the speaker, their reputation, social status, degree of conviction, or any other arbitrary factor unrelated to the propositional content, obviously are not considered as a truth condition; but they may enhance plausibility. As I have mentioned before, anecdotes are not testimonials (at least in the legal sense). Specific questions are considered to prevent the testimony from becoming an anecdote; to maintain or preserve any factual content that might be ascertained through the testimony (from the Wikipedia Page).

When a witness is asked a question, the opposing attorney can raise an objection:

  • argumentative
  • asked and answered
  • best evidence rule
  • calls for speculation
  • calls for a conclusion
  • compound question or narrative
  • hearsay
  • inflammatory
  • incompetent witness (e.g., child, mental or physical impairment, intoxicated)
  • irrelevant, immaterial (the words "irrelevant" and "immaterial" have the same meaning under the Federal Rules of Evidence. Historically, irrelevant evidence referred to evidence that has no probative value, i.e., does not tend to prove any fact. Immaterial refers to evidence that is probative, but not as to any fact material to the case. See Black's Law Dictionary, 7th Ed.).
  • lack of foundation
  • leading question
  • privilege
  • vague
  • ultimate issue testimony

There may also be an objection to the answer, including:

  • non-responsive

Many of these rules are designed to specifically reduce the chances of testimony becoming something of an anecdote. If we are specifically interested in maintaining the integrity of the factual information testified by an individual, we have to apply rigorous filtering methods to avoid any degradation. It is crucial to remember that these are not facts themselves, but statements affirming a fact. Consider an induvial giving testimony that they have an alibi so they could not have possibly committed a crime that occurred. They state that they were at the movie theaters, but upon further investigation we see no transaction on their credit card, video footage of them entering the establishment, and we have a receipt showing they were at a store 50 miles away from the movie theater they claimed to be at (they could not have possibly got to the move in time). Their claim of fact is indeed completely undermined by actual facts and evidence that we can use to infer the truth of their claims. In other words, even if testimony passes our filters, it can still be incredibly unreliable. This is the difference between direct evidence and inference from taking someone’s word. Think about it in even more depth; testimony about something factual cannot possibly serve to establish a scientific causal generalization for these exact issues. Testimony is not a fact; it is a statement about what is allegedly a fact. For scientific inference, you need direct evidence.

There is an explosion of information one can ask about the credibility of testimony as you begin to traverse down the tree structure. Many people stop at the root node but fail to realize that the credibility of a person making some claim also depends on the credibility of the sources they use to establish their claim. In the second image we can see that we begin with the “testimonial evidence” node and work our way down. Equivocal testimonies are those which contain multiple interpretations or conflicting accounts of some claim. These are highly questionable and typically disregarded. I show these images, the argumentation schemes, and the critical questions to point to the fact that there is considerable vetting that needs to be done before accepting a testimony and we can still be (and are frequently) misled by it. Testimonies cannot contribute to scientific research. Furthermore, anecdotes are of even lower quality than testimony because it is a rhetorical persuasive device.


The key point to all of this is that testimonials and anecdotes are not just something you encounter in the courtroom. You should understand their effects and relationship with persuasion in every day life. In some sense its almost impossible to divorce yourself from anecdote, it seems fundamental to human communication. We form all kinds of beliefs based on anecdotes and they affect our behaviors in very subtle ways especially when they go unchecked. I remember an instance when I was younger. Someone was telling a story about a person they knew who died while driving on a “dangerous road”. The presumption implicit in the anecdote was that the cause of death was somehow due to this road being unsafe. I remember hearing this when I was very young, and sure enough I always avoided this road. It wasn’t until I was forced to use the road, with the utmost cautiousness, that I realized the belief was irrational. Unsafe driving conditions persist across many roads, having a phobia of a specific road based on an anecdote was irrational because by that very logic I should have been frightened of the freeway.

What I am trying to say is that anecdotes and story telling are inherently tied to the human condition. We simply cannot do without them, but we must understand their place in relation to objective, universal, factual, scientific, and verifiable truths that are discovered or deduced systematically with rigorous methodology. Anecdotes allow us to share our experiences with one another. It would be foolish to subject anecdotes to these sorts of standards in all contexts. Anecdotes and metaphors orient our minds towards the more nebulous and existential aspects of life, but if they conflict with the systematized methods that have been demonstrated to work, you might want to reconsider your relation to the anecdote. I am not saying that I am “free from the effects of stupid anecdotes” and that I am 100 percent “only aligned with that which is objectively verifiable”; no one is. What I try to do is assess whether the implications of the anecdote will have significant implications for my own life if I accept it. If it does, then I will critically evaluate it more than a less impactful anecdote, because accepting it and making decisions based off something that is false will probably lead to a poor outcome. The point is that anecdotes are persuasive in ways that testimony and evidence are not. Persuasive stories are designed to orient your behavior towards or away from certain ends; they are goal oriented. If I am going to consider one that has a significant impact on my life, I better be sure there is something there other than rhetorical devices. The Epistemology of Testimony is very interesting; when are you justified in believing something when it is based off testimony?

Now I want to move on to how we should go about evaluating claims based on isolated or small number of instances. We will look at the Case Study (See No. 46).

  1. ‘Case-study is the study of the particularity and complexity of a single case, coming to understand its activity within important circumstances.’ Stake (1995, p.xi)
  2. ‘Case-study is an ‘intensive study of a single unit for the purpose of understanding a larger class of units’ Gerring (2004)
  3. ‘Case-study is an empirical inquiry that: Yin (2009, p.18) Investigates a contemporary phenomenon in depth and within its real-life context, especially when The boundaries between the phenomenon and context are not clearly evident.’
  4. ‘An in-depth exploration, from multiple perspectives, of the complexity and uniqueness of a particular project, policy, institution, programme or system in a real-life context. (Case study) is research based, inclusive of different methods and is evidence-led. (its) primary purpose is to generate in-depth understanding of a specific topic, programme, policy, institution, or system to generate knowledge and/or inform policy development, professional practice and civil or community action’        Simons (2009, p. 21)

There are many variations of the Case Study, including the Case Control Study. The key point is that the sample is small, participants are deliberately chosen, and we are studying them “in the wild” so to speak outside of a laboratory context. The data is individualized, we are not interested in studying sample or population parameters or introducing controlled interventions. This could be particularly useful for phenomena that are incredibly rare; the event is so infrequent that we simply cannot conduct an experiment.

I want to note that this is not the same as a Case Report, these are professional narratives that document notable observations but lack the systematic methodology required to infer something more broad. In essence, they are not studies; they are an anecdote delivered by a professional. They perform the same function as other anecdotes, development of hypotheses. However, given their nature they are highly susceptible to publication bias so there are standards around how to present the information, how to qualify the conclusions, mandates for specific information such as duration/timeline, etc. (see No. 54). Case Series methods are a generalization, but still suffer from problems such as Observer Bias, Selection Bias, Placebo Effect, and Hawthorne Effect.

Case studies lack generalizability. However, they incorporate feedback from participants in verbal form in a structured manner to eliminate issues with anecdotes. This is similar to how the legal system qualifies the use of testimonials and puts them through a rigorous selection process before admitting them to court. Case studies do the same, in that they provide structure to prevent all of the obvious ways word of mouth feedback can skew results. The key to causal generalization is prevention of bias and confounding; the best way to achieve this is through randomized control trials and systematic meta-analyses. You can add more structure, as in the case of prospective cohort study, retrospective cohort study, and nested case-control study but the same issues persist if you want to make some sort of inference from the information rather than just describe. You want to prevent story-telling.

Anyway, I am getting tired of writing about this. Be skeptical of anecdotes but be aware that sometimes it’s the best we have. But also, be aware that sometimes you don’t have to make a decision if all you have is anecdotes. If you have time to collect more quality information, you can simply withhold judgment. Sometimes, certain questions don’t lend themselves to statistical analysis like in the case of an Ethnography. Nevertheless, there was at least an effort to make the information collection process more rigorous. You should too. I’ve listed below some of the obvious ways second-hand data collection could be problematic. Perhaps if there are many issues  with the data collection process, and time is of the essence, you might need to rely on low quality information such as anecdotes. I would advise keeping your options open; you wouldn’t want to make a life-changing irreversible decision on the basis of low quality evidence.

Additional Resources:

  1. Data Science Lesson 1: Data versus Anecdote
  2. The Plural of Anecdote is not Data
  3. The Weakness of One
  4. Selection Bias in Observational and experimental studies
  5. A Catalog of Bias in Questionnaires
  6. Anecdotal Evidence
  7. Survivorship Bias
  8. Significance Levels
  9. Importance of Statistics
  10. Sorry Folks, the Plural of Anecdote is Data
  11. Survey Methodology
  12. When and why do people act on flawed science? Effects of anecdotes and prior beliefs on evidence-based decision-making
  13. The Case Study Approach
  14. Data Generation
  15. The Plural Of Anecdote is Misinformation
  16. Types of Evidence
  17. The Plural of Anecdote is not data, please mind the gap between virtual and real life
  18. Qualitative Methods in Implementation Research: An Introduction
  19. Qualitative Research
  20. Observer Bias
  21. Case Study
  22. Case Report
  23. Case Control Study
  24. Case Series
  25. Qualitative Study
  26. How to use and assess qualitative research methods
  27. Qualitative Research: Data Collection, Analysis, and Management
  28. Presenting and Evaluating Qualitative Research
  29. Qualitative Methods in Implementation Research: An Introduction
  30. Extending the sufficient component cause model to describe the Stable Unit Treatment Value Assumption (SUTVA)
  31. Is data the plural of anecdote? Inductive arguments in composition
  32. Herding, social influence and economic decision-making: socio-psychological and neuroscientific analyses
  33. Anecdotes (The Body of Evidence)
  34. When is Statistical Evidence Superior to Anecdotal Evidence in Supporting Probability Claims? The Role of Argument Type
  35. Why Eye Witness Testimony is Unreliable
  36. Philosophy of Testimony
  37. Eyewitness Testimony and Memory Bias
  38. Evaluating Arguments
  39. Science Versus Anecdotal Evidence
  40. Epistemology of Testimony
  41. Standards for Reporting Qualitative Research: A Synthesis of Recommendations
  42. Case Selection Techniques in Case Study Research
  43. Case Studies And Theory Development In The Social Sciences
  44. Guidelines to the Writing of Case Studies
  45. Enhancing the quality of case studies in health services research.
  46. Lessons learnt: examining the use of case study methodology for nursing research in the context of palliative care
  47. Epidemiology in Practice: Case-Control Studies
  48. Case Control Studies
  49. Methodology Series Module 2: Case-control Studies
  50. Methodology or method? A critical review of qualitative case study reports
  51. Distinguishing case study as a research method from case reports as a publication type
  52. Continuing to enhance the quality of case study methodology in health services research
  53. Case Reports, Case Series – From Clinical Practice to Evidence-Based Medicine in Graduate Medical Education
  54. The CARE Guidelines
  55. Case Study Research: Principles and Practices

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

The Nature of Agnosticism Part 1

The Nature of Agnosticism Part 2

Basic Considerations for Argument and Evidence Evaluation