Toulmin Argumentation Model

 I was exposed to Stephen Toulmin during a second year course at University on critical thinking. This class was radically transformative; awakening me to the practice and application of critical thinking. Much of my time in school had revolved around uncritically absorbing information presented to me during powerpoint lectures, reading a textbook, or completing problem sets. After exposure to different forms of argument evaluation, patterns of reasoning, skepticism, introspection, forms of evidence, forms of explanation, certainty vs uncertainty, free thought, critical questioning, the Socratic Method, argument analysis, debating, rhetoric, higher order thinking, intellectual humility, elements of interpretation and many other features of critical thought, I became extremely confident in my thinking. 

This propelled me forward in my other studies. I could actually start to see the bigger picture, how different disciplines interconnect, deeper principles governing whole academic traditions, and potential weaknesses and limitations. Rather than seeing disciplines as these abstract domains of truth bearers, I saw them as large collections of people trying to answer specific questions using evidence and reasons. Each one had specific methods accessible to them, but there was a core feature relating all of the domains (in the sciences specifically, causal relations). I too, could take part in this, in order to not only remember, but to know, and apply it to situations in my life, and even contribute. It was this explosion of potential I never knew I had. It was lurking beneath the surface somewhere in my brain, and it was not until exposure to the Toulmin model of argumentation that I started to chip away at the barrier limiting me. 

I think the main advantage of the scheme, is that it lays out a common form of reasoning in a very clear way. Lets start with the basic structure:



So lets start with the ultimate objective: some claim is being made with respect to some field or domain. The claim can be anything; some may call it an "opinion", "thesis", or "point". It is a proposition you wish to demonstrate as true, false, likely, unlikely, relevant, etc. Apart from simply asserting what you think, you will need some "data" or "evidence" to ground your assertion in reality. The data is different from the claim and does not speak for itself. Many different conclusions can be drawn from and about a set of information. Evidence is in some sense, underdetermined; what we have available to us might be insufficient to form an attitude towards a proposition. In some cases, evidence is overdetermined; hand prints on a weapon and DNA evidence are not BOTH needed, one piece of evidence may be enough. Why is it we can automatically make the conclusion that the presence of DNA is sufficient to prove beyond reasonable doubt that the defendant committed some crime? This is where the notion of Warrant stands out. This is the "relevance rule" that glues together the data and claim. These are typically unstated assumptions of cause-effect that can be informed by our world-view, experience, experiments, common sense, social conditioning, or maybe a set of prior arguments that you internalized as true. Identifying a warrant can sometimes be challenging because you typically take it for granted. Why does DNA automatically stand as "proof"? The warrant is that, if DNA is present, this guarantees you were at the location of the crime. DNA is unique to an individual with the exception of twins and we typically rule out cases where someone planted your DNA at a crime scene. These seem to be very unlikely exceptional circumstances; so beyond reasonable doubt DNA is strongly connected to whatever the assertion is. Warrants can also be much less reliable; which is typically the case. Suppose you wish to make the claim that we need to raise taxes. You point to levels of employment and social happiness indexes in Scandinavian countries. The warrant, if explicated, will likely be "what is applicable in northern European countries will also be applicable in the United States" which ties the evidence to your conclusion. Of course, the warrant can be examined and probed. This is known as your Backing. What makes you so sure that the conditions in one country generalize to another? Typically, general forms of evidence will be used to support a warrant; as can be seen with the example below. In general, your claim can be qualified; the scope of it can be limited. This will keep the force of your claim in line with the mass and force of whatever backing and warrant you provide. 


You can apply this structure to anything really. Suppose we hear an announcement that Ford has flooded the market with new trucks. I wish to claim that the market price of trucks will rapidly decline. Why can I make this claim? Because of the theory of supply and demand. Generally speaking, according to the set of assumptions given to us in the theory of competitive firms, equilibrium prices will decline assuming demand for the product remains constant. My grounds are going to be a specific report that Ford, as a matter of fact, increased production. My backing for my warrant can come from evidence in Economics literature; or a rigorous theoretical justification (depending on who your audience is). Essentially, you have a claim and you wish to show that the conditions which make your claim true, are in fact instantiated. 
The core idea is that a warrant is what connects everything together when reasoning and convincing. The practice of critical thinking is not just being able to verify if some set of data is reliable, or that the argument is logically sound. Crucially, it involves analyzing these unstated warrants. This is what truly tunes your critical thinking. Lets suppose the claim is that we need to have the federal government mandate a nation wide ban on E-cigarettes on the basis that N percent of teenagers have gained access to them. You have the claim (C) and the data (D); but what is the warrant (W) here and the backing? Can there be alternative conclusions drawn given the same dataset but different warrants? This is excluding any notion of "should". Whether we should or should not do something in this case is irrelevant (or maybe not if you can make a case). The question is the "How". Can different warrants lead to different policy recommendations? One common principle, that can be seen as a warrant, is commonly used in scientific reasoning. Occams Razor, is a principle of parsimony. The idea is that if you have two competing hypothesis that equally support a prediction (or claim), then the one with fewer assumptions (is more parsimonious) should be the one we choose. There are other conditions for acceptability such as Falsifiability. Can you think of ways to argue against well founded warrants like these? 

Here are two more examples in action:

I don't think it is always obvious for us to probe into the reasoning behind the beliefs we hold; or why we even should. Many of us are brought up simply to think that whatever we hold to be true, is true. We are convinced, almost as a dogma, that self-doubt is inherently a bad thing. Critical assessment of ourselves is actually enlightening. This model gives us a standard to evaluate arguments. You can begin to see how you apply criticisms to others while withholding them from yourself. This asymmetry and double-standard way of thinking, for me at least, was incredible to overcome. 

Many people also hold the idea that they have to commit themselves to the strongest view of whatever they think is true. Qualifying what you claim, or limiting the scope of your claim, is far from weak. It makes you more in-tune with reality. In fact, it gives you more precision and more confidence, since the true scope of the claim is preserved. In Uses of Argument, Toulmin does not intend these to be precise probability estimates. In practical argument this is almost impossible. "It may be" does not mean you have to show a probability within a 1-2% margin for example; just to show that in principle something is possible. This is amazing because it can help you recalibrate your degree of conviction; just by making explicit your warrants, backing, and data. 


Here is what it looks like in practice:


The rebuttal premise is key, because it makes explicit the conditions in which your inference might be incorrect. This is important because you make it known how you can be wrong; which is intellectually humble. Your conclusion in this scenario, can be a premise or backing in another argument, or part of a larger argument in which this argument is simply a component. The key idea is that the Toulmin model shows the very basic schematic for all field-dependent reasoning. The idea of field dependency is important. Toulmin talks about how almost all forms of reasoning, with the exception of mathematics, follows this sort of pattern. The latter is characterized as field invariant. 

Toulmin was a critic of absolutism and relativism. The word "invariant" means constant, unchanging, or unaffected. Field variant means that the methods of determining truth may differ vastly among chemists, children, historians, lawyers, politicians, economists etc, thus, their means of arguing and their premise. While field invariant arguments can be used in many contexts and across many fields (universal truths). So, does this mean that if the truth value of a claim depends on the context, we are subject to radical relativism? Or that if the only certainty we can gain is from axiomatic mathematical reasoning, we cannot gain any knowledge? This "dichotomy" is what Toulmin is specifically arguing against. Practical reasoning is not simply relativistic or absolutist; it has to be something else. 


 If you think about it, its obvious. There are different methods of determining truth in different domains. Do we apply the same standards in law as we do in scientific inquiry? It would be hard to claim that we do, and that if we do not, that both are simply relativistic. It would also be absurd to think we can apply models of deductive reasoning from philosophical logic to something like law. Normative conditions vary from field to field; this sounds a lot like Wittgenstein's language games (of whom Toulmin was a student). Think if field dependency at the level of the warrant. Toulmin's general "way of arguing" to me, seems almost universal. The warrant you instantiate, however, seems to be the field dependent component. The rules governing which generalizations or principles that are valid, appear to be contingent upon the field with respect to its origin. This also makes sense. Why is it that, someone asserting a cause and effect relationship about a medicine outside the field of epidemiology (or something) is regarded as suspect or unfounded? Well, because the field dependency is apparent. If your backing for a warrant absent any randomized trials, we have reason to suspect that the warrant is fragile. 

In the introduction to Readings in Argumentation, there is a section I find illuminating. 


?

Toulmin  first advanced  the notion  of "argument  fields" in  his  book  The  Uses  of  Argument   (1958; cf. Toulmin,  1972; Toulmin, Rieke  &  Janik,  1979). He suggested  that  some features or characteristics  of  argument are field invariant (occur and/or are used in the same way wherever argument  occurs), while others are field dependent  (vary  from field to field). This  is an  intriguing  idea,  and,  if     correct,  it     is  useful for argument  critics and  theorists  to identify which  aspects  of   argument are field invariant, as well as to specify the various  argument  fields and  the field dependent  features of  argument  found  in   each.  While this project may seem fairly straight-forward,  two  important  questions arise. First, which characteristics  of argument  should  we  examine,  in order  to determine  whether  they are field invariant  or  dependent?  Among the many choices available are: (1) components of   an argument (data, reasoning, claims, qualifiers, etc.); (2) procedures (rules,  presumption,  order  of  speeches,  etc.); (3) styles  of  arguing,  and  (4)  strategies  in  advocacy.  Any  distinction  that  we  can  make  concerning arguments and arguing could serve as the basis for inquiry into field invariant  and dependent  traits. However,  these  possibilities  may not necessarily vary between different fields. That is, procedures might differ, but components might not. The field theorist or critic must  decide  which  characteristics  of  argument  to  examine.  Second, we must decide how to divide up discourse into argument fields. They could, for example, be defined by academic  specialties  (economics, politics, law, etc.). However, should political arguments made by politicians about, say, the annual budget, be considered  to  occur  in  a separate  field from the  arguments  of  political  scientists  who  try  to  understand  the  budget-making  process?  Furthermore,  would the argumentation of ordinary people about government spending and  taxation  be  considered  yet  another  field? Another  example  to  indicate the difficulties inherent in defining argument fields concerns doctors  and  economists.  When  doctors  argue  about  medicine  and  economists  argue  about  economics  we  have  two  different  fields.  However,  when  doctors  and  economists  dispute  about   medical   economics is   that a third field, or two additional ones?

So, it is not that obvious what counts as field invariant. Nevertheless, it is a really useful conceptualization when learning how to critically think. You can start to probe into how different fields establish warrants for claims. Mainly because the very question of "what makes this an argument field" enables inquiry into how the field establishes knowledge. This provides the critical thinker with a level of insight into how the knowledge is formed, to what extent the knowledge is based on clear methodology, and why some expert advice seems to run contrary to our common sense assumptions. Our warrants may conflict with those by established professionals; and we can resolve these discrepancies by asking how they came to their conclusions. The Toulmin model provides that general base to work from. 

As an example, why do medical researchers tend to ignore anecdotal reports about the effect of a drug but during ordinary debate people find this convincing? Medical researchers have reason to rule this out as irrelevant when establishing the causal effect of a drug; strong arguments from probability theory and experimental design. The warrant is not arbitrary, or relativistic. This standard, however, seems to be universal to all fields interested in cause and effect; but a cause-effect relation is never "proven" in a formal, mathematical, universal sense. When a critical thinker engages with someone at the dinner table, or watches the news, or reads a politically charged news post, they can understand why certain warrants are invalid and field dependent warrants established by researchers might prove more reliable. The non expert might say something like; D: I was sick before I ate this apple, and now I am not C: Apples cure this sickness. W: My first hand experience is the most legitimate form of evidence in questions of cause and effect. The expert will say; D: Subject got sick and then ate an apple and subsequently got better. W: Experiential evidence is subject to confounding, non-reproducibility, and regression to the mean. Furthermore, we may have reason to think the anecdotal experience is biased or subject to causal fallacies. C: It is unlikely that the apple caused anything, additional research is needed. 

To summarize, here are the components detailed in the Wikipedia page and some examples I found on the internet:

Claim (Conclusion)
A conclusion whose merit must be established. In argumentative essays, it may be called the thesis.[11] For example, if a person tries to convince a listener that he is a British citizen, the claim would be "I am a British citizen" (1).
Ground (Fact, Evidence, Data)
A fact one appeals to as a foundation for the claim. For example, the person introduced in 1 can support his claim with the supporting data "I was born in Bermuda" (2).
Warrant
A statement authorizing movement from the ground to the claim. In order to move from the ground established in 2, "I was born in Bermuda", to the claim in 1, "I am a British citizen", the person must supply a warrant to bridge the gap between 1 and 2 with the statement "A man born in Bermuda will legally be a British citizen" (3).
Backing
Credentials designed to certify the statement expressed in the warrant; backing must be introduced when the warrant itself is not convincing enough to the readers or the listeners. For example, if the listener does not deem the warrant in 3 as credible, the speaker will supply the legal provisions: "I trained as a barrister in London, specialising in citizenship, so I know that a man born in Bermuda will legally be a British citizen".
Rebuttal (Reservation)
Statements recognizing the restrictions which may legitimately be applied to the claim. It is exemplified as follows: "A man born in Bermuda will legally be a British citizen, unless he has betrayed Britain and has become a spy for another country".
Qualifier
Words or phrases expressing the speaker's degree of force or certainty concerning the claim. Such words or phrases include "probably", "possible", "impossible", "certainly", "presumably", "as far as the evidence goes", and "necessarily". The claim "I am definitely a British citizen" has a greater degree of force than the claim "I am a British citizen, presumably". (See also: Defeasible reasoning.)



The main point: All arguments rest upon unstated assumptions, or in Toulmin terms, Warrants. In some sense, a claim can only be comprehended, if it corresponds with a presupposed warrant. Its as if a warrant is your mechanism for making sense of new data and inferences from that data. Many people will say "The facts are the facts" or "the facts speak for themselves"; no they do not. If we agree on the facts, great. But the question is: How do you get to your conclusion? What is your glue, or process for connecting the ultimate claim to "the facts"? How does the data support the claim? This is not a question of "more" data, but the nature of the justification process. You have to show that: These facts are relevant, are enough, and the right ones to get to your claim. This is the hard part that people take for granted. This is exactly what Toulmin points out in his writings and is obvious once you lay out the structure of argument.

The Toulmin model subsumes all other forms of argument, you can literally map all forms of argument to this structure; especially defeasible ones (which I think pretty much all argument categorizes as anyway). This is so powerful; it reminds me of the universality of a Turing machine. Lets take an example of the abductive argumentation scheme from Douglas Walton and map it onto Toulmin model. To start lets make a distinction:

Abductive, presumptive and plausible arguments

  • Deductive Reasoning: Suppose a bag contains only red marbles, and you take one out. You may infer by deductive reasoning that the marble is red. 
  • Inductive Reasoning: Suppose you do not know the color of the marbles in the bag, and you take one out and it is red. You may infer by inductive reasoning that all the marbles in the bag are red. 
  • Abductive Reasoning: Suppose you find a red marble in the vicinity of a bag of red marbles. You may infer by abductive reasoning that the marble is from the bag.

In this example, the abductive process can be thought of like this:

  • Positive Data: the red marble is on the floor, near the bag of red marbles. 
  • Hypothesis: the red marble came from the bag. 
  • Negative Data: no other relevant facts suggest any other plausible hypothesis that would explain where the red marble came from. 
  • Conclusion: the hypothesis that the red marble came from the bag is the best guess.

The scheme Walton finds in the literature:

  • D is a collection of data. 
  • H explains D. 
  • No other hypothesis can explain D as well as H does. 
  • Therefore H is probably true.

Some critical questions:

  1. how decisively H surpasses the alternatives 
  2. how good H is by itself, independently of considering the alternatives (we should be cautious about accepting a hypothesis, even if it is clearly the best one we have, if it is not sufficiently plausible in itself) 
  3.  judgments of the reliability of the data 
  4. how much confidence there is that all plausible explanations have been considered (how thorough was the search for alternative explanations) 
  5. pragmatic considerations, including the costs of being wrong, and the benefits of being right 
  6. how strong the need is to come to a conclusion at all, especially considering the possibility of seeking further evidence before deciding.

And a modern version proposed by Walton:

  • F is a finding or given set of facts. 
  • E is a satisfactory explanation of F. 
  • No alternative explanation E' given so far is as satisfactory as E. 
  • Therefore, E is plausible, as a hypothesis

And the corresponding critical questions:

  • CQl : How satisfactory is E itself as an explanation of F, apart from the alternative explanations available so far in the dialogue? 
  • CQ2: How much better an explanation is E than the alternative explanations available so far in the dialogue? 
  • CQ3: How far has the dialogue progressed? If the dialogue is an inquiry, how thorough has the search been in the investigation of the case? 
  • CQ4: Would it be better to continue the dialogue further, instead of drawing a conclusion at this point? 

Lets transpose this on to the Toulmin model:

  • C: Red marble came from this bag
  • Q: Probably, presumably
  • D: There is a red marble on the floor within the vicinity of this bag full of red marbles.
  • W: It is generally not a coincidence that something found on a floor resembles the rest of a collection in a nearby bag; or was put there deliberately.
  • B: Common sense, no reason to believe otherwise. Appeals to general intuition. How things "Generally work"

Now lets suppose you have some reason for overriding W and B. This is the R (Rebuttal) part of Toulmin's model, and the critical question aspect proposed by Walton. Suppose the dialogue proceeds and we find that another person was in the room, and spilled their own separate bag of marbles and didn't fully clean up the mess. Well, this overrides the original claim. This is a silly example but it extrapolates to complex cases that effect our lives. 

The key idea is to start thinking about your thinking. I never really did that until introduced to frameworks for doing this. 






Comments

Popular posts from this blog

The Nature of Agnosticism Part 1

The Nature of Agnosticism Part 2

Basic Considerations for Argument and Evidence Evaluation